Skip to main content
Log in

Readings of scalar particles: noch/still

  • Published:
Linguistics and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The paper develops a uniform compositional analysis of the various readings of the scalar particle still and its German counterpart noch. Noch/still is a presuppositional scalar particle that gives rise to implicatures. Interpretive possibilities arise through different choices for the scale that the particle associates with, different attachment sites in the syntax, and interaction with focus. These interpretive parameters allow for a wide range of possible sentence interpretations, which overlap, but do not coincide for still and noch. The contrastive perspective allows us to examine the role of scales in the grammar. The implicatures triggered by the scalar item open an interesting perspective for the generation of implicatures in general.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Abrusan, M. (2016). Presupposition cancellation: Explaining the soft-hard distinction. Natural Language Semantics,24(2), 165–202. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-016-9122-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abusch, D. (2002). Lexical alternatives as a source of pragmatic presuppositions. Proceedings of SALT, 12, 1–19.

  • Bade, N., & Sachs, K. (2018). EXH passes on alternatives—A comment on Fox & Spector. To appear in Natural Language Semantics.

  • Beaver, D., & Clark, B. (2008). Sense and sensitivity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Beck, S. (2006a). Intervention effects follow from focus interpretation. Natural Language Semantics,14(1), 1–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beck, S. (2006b). Focus on again. Linguistics and Philosophy,29(3), 277–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beck, S. (2007). Quantifier dependent readings of anaphoric presuppositions. In U. Sauerland & P. Stateva (Eds.), Presupposition and implicature in compositional semantics (pp. 12–33). New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Beck, S. (2011). Comparison constructions. In C. Maienborn, K. von Heusinger, & P. Portner (Eds.), Semantics: An international handbook of natural language meaning (Vol. 2, pp. 1341–1389). Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck, S. (2016a). Focus sensitive operators. In C. Féry & S. Ishihara (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of information structure. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck, S. (2016b). Temporal noch/still and further-to readings of German noch. In N. Bade, P. Berezovskaya & A. Schöller (Eds.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 20 (pp. 4–25). Tübingen: Universität Tübingen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck, S. (2016c). Discourse related readings of scalar particles. Proceedings of SALT,26, 142–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, G., Danny, F., & Benjamin, S. (2011). The grammatical view of scalar implicatures and the relationship between semantics and pragmatics. In C. Maienborn, P. Portner, & K. von Heusinger (Eds.), Semantics: An international handbook of natural language meaning (Vol. 3, pp. 2297–2332). Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cresswell, M. J. (1978). Prepositions and points of view. Linguistics and Philosophy,2(1), 1–41. https://doi.org/10.1007/bf00365129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crnic, L. (2011). Getting even. PhD dissertation, MIT.

  • Crnic, L., Chemla, E., & Fox, D. (2015). Scalar implicatures of embedded disjunction. Natural Language Semantics,23(3), 271–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fanselow, G., & Lenertova, D. (2011). Left peripheral focus. Mismatches between syntax and information structure. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory,29(1), 169–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, D. (2007). Free Choice and the theory of scalar implicatures. In U. Sauerland & P. Stateva (Eds.), Presupposition and implicature in compositional semantics (pp. 71–120). New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, D., & Katzir, R. (2011). On the characterization of alternatives. Natural Language Semantics,26(1), 87–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, D., & Spector, B. (2018). Economy and embedded exhaustification. Natural Language Semantics,19(1), 1–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenberg, Y. (2010). Additivity in the domain of eventualities. In: M. Prinzhorn, V. Schmitt, & S. Zobel (Eds.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung (Vol. 14, pp. 151–167). Vienna: Universität Wien.

  • Hamblin, C. L. (1973). Questions in montague english. Foundations of Language,10(1), 41–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I. (1990). Presupposition projection. In R. van der Sandt (Ed.), Reader for Nijmegen workshop on presupposition. Nijmegen: University of Nijmegen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I., & Kratzer, A. (1998). Semantics in generative grammar. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohaus, V. (2012). Directed motion as comparison: Evidence from Samoan. In E. Bogal-Allbritten (Ed.), Proceedings of SULA 6 (pp. 335–348). Amherst, MA: GLSA.

  • Howell, A. (2018). More on the grammar of alternatives. PhD dissertation, Universität Tübingen.

  • Howell, A., Hohaus, V., Berezovskaya, P., Braun, J. Durmaz, S., Sachs, K., & Beck, S. (2018). (No) variation in the grammar of alternatives. Ms. Universität Tübingen.

  • Ippolito, M. (2007). On the meaning of some focus-sensitive particles. Natural Language Semantics,15(1), 1–34. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-007-9004-0..

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H., & Rossdeutscher, A. (1994). DRS-construction and lexically driven inference. Theoretical Linguistics,20(2–3), 165–235.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, W. (2007/2015). Über die Partikeln schon und noch. Talk given at the U. Tübingen. (Based on Wolfgang Klein. 2007. About the German particles schon and noch. Manuscript).

  • Kluge, F. (1995). Etymologisches Wörterbuch der deutschen Sprache. 23rd, enl. edn. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

  • König, E. (1977). Temporal and non-temporal uses of schon and noch in German. Linguistics and Philosophy,1(2), 173–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • König, E. (1991). Gradpartikeln. In A. von Stechow & D. Wunderlich (Eds.), Semantik / Semantics (pp. 786–803). Berlin: Mouton De Gruyter.

  • Kratzer, A. (1998). More structural analogies between pronouns and tenses. Proceedings of SALT, 8, 92–110.

  • Krifka, M. (1995). The semantics and pragmatics of polarity items. Linguistic Analysis,25, 1–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (1998). The origins of telicity. In S. Rothstein (Ed.), Events and grammar (pp. 197–235). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (2000). Alternatives for aspectual particles: Semantics of still and already. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society.

  • Löbner, S. (1989). German schonerstnoch: An integrated analysis. Linguistics and Philosophy,12(2), 167–212. https://doi.org/10.1007/bf00627659.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Löbner, S. (1990). Wahr neben Falsch. Duale Operatoren als die Quantoren natürlicher Sprache. Tübingen: Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menendez-Benito, P. (2010). On universal free choice items. Natural Language Semantics,18(1), 33–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelis, L. (1993). Continuity within three scalar models: The polysemy of adverbial still. Journal of Semantics,10 (3), 193–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mittwoch, A. (1993). The relationship between schon/already and noch/still: A reply to Löbner. Natural Language Semantics,2(1), 71–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Patel-Grosz, P., & Beck, S. (accepted). Different again. Semantics and Pragmatics.

  • Rooth, M. (1985). Association with focus. PhD dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.

  • Rooth, M. (1992). A theory of focus interpretation. Natural Language Semantics,1(1), 75–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sauerland, U. (2004). Scalar implicatures in complex sentences. Linguistics and Philosophy,27(3), 367–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schimmelpfennig, L. (2015). Diachronic development of still—A corpus study from middle english to early modern english. State exam thesis, Universität Tübingen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (1989). Presupposition. In D. Gabbay & F. Günthner (Eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spector, B. (2010). Topics in the semantics of interrogative clauses, hand-out 3, Vienna, March 2010. Available at: http://lumie​re.ens.fr/~bspec​tor/Quest​ions2​010. Accessed 6 Sept 2017.

  • Thomas, G. (2010). Incremental more. Proceedings of SALT, 20, 233–250.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, G. (2018). Underspecification in degree operators. Journal of Semantics,35(1), 43–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tiemann, S., Kirsten, M., Beck, S., Hertrich, I., & Rolke, B. (2015). Presupposition processing and accommodation: An experiment on wieder (‘again’) and consequences for other. In T. F. Schwarz (Ed.), Experimental perspectives on presuppositions (pp. 39–65). Heidelberg: Springer.

  • Tonhauser, J., Beaver, D., Roberts, C., & Simons, M. (2013). Toward a taxonomy of projective content. Language,89(1), 66–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trinh, T., & Haida, A. (2015). Constraining the derivation of alternatives. Natural Language Semantics,23(4), 249–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Truckenbrodt, H. (2013). An analysis of prosodic F-effects in interrogatives: Prosody, syntax and semantics. Lingua,124, 131–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Umbach, C. (2009a). Another additive particle under stress: German additive noch. In Proceedings of the 10th Symposium on Logic and Language (LoLa 10) (pp. 149–156). Budapest: Hungarian Academy of Science.

  • Umbach, C. (2009b). Comparatives combined with additive particles: The case of German noch. In A. Riester & T. Solstad (Ed.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 13 (pp. 543–558). Stuttgart: OPUS.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Stechow, A. (2009). Tenses in compositional semantics. In W. Klein & P. Li (Eds.), The expression of time (pp. 129–166). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Stechow, A., & Beck, S. (2015). Events, times and worlds—An LF architecture. In C. Fortmann (Ed.), Situationsargumente im Nominalbereich (pp. 13–46). Berlin: De Gruyter.

  • von Stechow, A., & Sternefeld, W. (1988). Bausteine syntaktischen Wissens. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmermann, M. (2018). A unified semantics of schon as a degree operator. Journal of Semantics,21(2), 247–331.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmermann, T. E. (2000). Free choice disjunction and epistemic possibility. Natural Language Semantics,8(4), 255–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am very greatful to the editor Malte Zimmermann and to three anonymous reviewers, who were extremely helpful in improving the paper, from the first version I submitted to the present result. I would like to thank the participants of my Universität Tübingen seminars 2013, 2016 and 2018 for helpful discussion. Thank you also to the audiences at Universität Göttingen, MIT and UMass Amherst 2015, the STECHOW workshop at Sinn und Bedeutung 2015 and at SALT 2016. This research was supported by the DFG grant to the SFB 833.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sigrid Beck.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Beck, S. Readings of scalar particles: noch/still. Linguist and Philos 43, 1–67 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-018-09256-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-018-09256-1

Keywords

Navigation